Quantcast
Channel: IZT Library
Viewing all articles
Browse latest Browse all 32

Review: The Really Hard Problem, Flanagan 2007 - Tony Danford 2007

$
0
0

Owen Flanagan 2007 The Really Hard Problem – Meaning in a Material World. Cambridge Massachusetts: MIT Press.

Owen Flanagan1 is a naturalist – he believes that we are nothing but animals living in a material world free of any supernatural dimension – and he is not afraid to tackle the big questions. His overarching project appears to be consolatory: that denying God and the supernatural does not result in a world devoid of meaning, mystery or magic. He is strongly attracted to Buddhism, particularly Tibetan, and that combination of materialism and Buddhism is what attracted me to this book, even if only to see how the other (materialist) half lives.

His book asks the question: how can we live lives which are genuinely meaningful in a material world? He calls this work ‘Project Eudaimonia’, eudaimonia from the Greek meaning ‘happy spirit’ or as Flanagan translates it, ‘flourishing’. His contention is that this flourishing is empirically based and should be subject to empirical analysis – that is, resting on foundations which are located exclusively in the natural world. Virtue flows from learning from experience in the real world, not from the divine.

The book comes across as a polemic, sketching out a very wide territory without exhaustively arguing all the points. It sets out a rather recursive, discursive, and disjointed narrative, which may well be inevitable given the huge theme, but which made the arguments, although clear enough taken singly, rather difficult to build up into a coherent picture (and to review). A decent editor would have helped enormously. I was occasionally brought up short by anti-theistic statements: for example, that to seek to locate the source of a moral code in a divine standard is ‘immature, epistemically and emotionally irresponsible’ (p138). He is rather impatient of any world view which requires a supernatural foundation for a meaningful life. I respect his right to pronounce that there is no supernatural (without agreeing with it), but I did find his occasional tipping-over into outright insults unnecessary and unworthy of the rest of the book. That said, he’s certainly no reductive materialist or devotee of scientism, which he denounces as a ‘silly and puffed-up view that is not worth taking seriously’(p72). Take that, Dawkins!

Flanagan starts by reclaiming the topic of the good life, and how to live it, as the proper vocation of philosophy. (This is, of course, also a central concern of psychotherapy.) This is ‘Project Eudaimonia’. He then suggests a model which purports to describe the domain of meaning within which we all located2. By participating in this multifactorial domain of meaning, we make sense of things, orient ourselves, live meaningfully, through what he calls the psycho-poetic performance of our individual lives.

Flanagan goes on to assert that consciousness can be explained using only natural resources3. Next, free will (no stone is left unturned by Flanagan) comes under scrutiny. Does the scientific image spell death for free will? Yes, for the Western libertarian idea of unfettered free agency. No, for the more ancient idea of voluntary versus involuntary action: voluntary action is that initiated by the conscious analysis of prior experience. The will seems to be self-initiating but this is an illusion: our actions are voluntary but nonetheless still part of the causal nexus. Flanagan sees Buddhism as generally supporting this idea.

Having settled the big questions to his satisfaction, Flanagan continues with the main part of his thesis: the extraction of ethical norms from nature. He insists that ethical norms can be addressed empirically: human moral behaviour is the result of instincts and feelings endowed through Darwinian natural selection. Thankfully, Flanagan does not descend to the selfish gene level of debate, and states that there are now ‘credible accounts of how biological evolution could allow genuine psychological altruism’ (p47). He moves through a discussion of Plato, claiming that the Good, the Beautiful and the True are not timeless external Forms, but ‘works in progress, things we seek to make determinate within the constraints of natural orientations’(p56). We flourish as and when we pursue these works in progress. It is in our natures to seek such flourishing – we are ‘born with a thirst’ for it. The problem here is that Flanagan is not convincing in his account of the natural origins of this thirst for the good, beautiful and true: he simply says that a (scientific) account is still required but that it is ‘not that difficult’. Others might claim in the meantime that the thirst comes from God, or some other supernatural source.

In a sort of interlude, Flanagan now abruptly turns to a discussion of Buddhism and science. He sees the possibility of great mutual enrichment between the two traditions. Some reconciliation between Buddhism and science is possible because Buddhism is non-theistic and non-doctrinal. But he regards the Dalai Lama (who he has the greatest respect for) with some suspicion when the Dalai Lama points out the difference between not finding something (scientifically) and finding its non-existence. The immaterial mind and karma across rebirth are two such examples of the former: science cannot prove their non-existence, leaving Buddhism free to assert them, to Flanagan’s delicately expressed consternation over many pages of densely argued polemic4.

Now turning back to his main thesis, Flanagan seeks an empiricist foundation for the idea ‘that some ways of living and being are better than others’(p107). He finds the precedent for this in two ancient examples: Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics and the Abhidhamma. In both cases, one observes lives that work and lives that don’t work and one learns from them. Flanagan sees Aristotle’s virtues and the Buddha’s Four Divine Abodes as recommendations for ways of being/acting resulting from experience: they are proposed as virtues to be aspired to because they work. Flanagan is aware of the danger of circularity here: ethical norms are evaluated according to experience – desirable norms lead to flourishing – but the judgement of
flourishing itself involves applying ethical norms, and it’s not at all clear to me whether Flanagan avoids this danger. The problem is that Flanagan seeks an empirical method of making absolute moral evaluations of living - ‘some ways of living and being are better than others’ – but by basing virtue on empiricism alone, he makes it contingent, thereby removing any firm basis to finally evaluate any particular virtue or life. The absolute evaluations appear to rest on that hypothetical innate human thirst for the good, beautiful and true.

Missing out chapter 5 (which discusses neuroscience), we come to the last chapter which seeks to naturalise spirituality. Flanagan ranges very far and wide here in a haphazard way which makes succinct criticism impossible. Here’s one observation: although Flanagan sees belief in the supernatural as childish, he believes it does no harm as long as the supernatural is thought of as a myth rather than as a literally existing truth. Belief in a myth is not ‘true belief’(p193) – when we talk about myths ‘we are only talking about stories’ (p191). The implication is that only empirically verifiable information is worthy of ‘true belief’ and stories, although they may provide deep meaning, are (as sources of truth) morally suspect, not entirely virtuous, lightweight. So much for poetry, literature and all the other works of imagination which bring meaning to the rest of us. Meaning, magic and mystery are not so much naturalised as neutralised.

Notes
1 Flanagan was the researcher behind the story in 2003 about a meditating Buddhist monk showing ‘a remarkably frisky left pre-frontal cortex … a site well-correlated with reports of positive mood’ (p149). The press reported this at the time as showing that [Buddhist] meditation leads to happiness, and that the seat of happiness in the brain had been located. Flanagan remains properly sanguine about this.

2 This is a world of meaning constituted by a set of spaces of meaning {art, science, technology, ethics, politics, spirituality}, which he calls the Space of MeaningEarly 21st century. These six spaces of meaning are natural phenomena, the practices of humans, themselves natural creatures, and therefore should be
explicable through the natural sciences and human sciences. The sciences can therefore explain, in principle, the nature and function of {art, science, technology, ethics, politics, spirituality}.

3 Conscious mental events are ‘Janus-faced and uniquely so’: they are realized in objective neurological states and they have first person subjective feel - phenomenality. Each aspect necessarily implies the other. There is no particular mystery: that is simply how things are. But consciousness naturally subsists in brain processes: Flanagan has no truck with the concept of immaterial properties of mind.

4 Eg the randomness and lack of directionality in Darwinian evolution does not sit well with karma, and rebirth requires some sort of immaterial mind property which Flanagan has already rejected.

5  Courage, justice, temperance, wisdom, generosity, wit, friendliness, truthfulness, magnificence and greatness of soul.

6  Loving-kindness, compassion, appreciative joy and equanimity.


Tony Danford 2007


Viewing all articles
Browse latest Browse all 32

Trending Articles